UNIT II





UNIT  II

Ethics in all aspects of health care

Medical ethics is a system of moral principles that apply values and judgments to the practice of medicine. As a scholarly discipline, medical ethics encompasses its practical application in clinical settings as well as work on its history, philosophy, theology, and sociology.

A common framework used in the analysis of medical ethics is the "four principles" approach postulated by Tom Beauchamp and James Childress in their textbook Principles of biomedical ethics. It recognizes four basic moral principles, which are to be judged and weighed against each other, with attention given to the scope of their application. The four principles are:[6]
Respect for autonomy - the patient has the right to refuse or choose their treatment. (Voluntas aegroti suprema lex.) Beneficence - a practitioner should act in the best interest of the patient. (Salus aegroti suprema lex.)

Justice - concerns the distribution of scarce health resources, and the decision of who gets what treatment (fairness and equality).
Other values which are sometimes discussed include:
Respect for persons - the patient (and the person treating the patient) have the right to be treated with dignity.
Truthfulness and honesty - the concept of informed consent has increased in importance since the historical events of the Doctors' Trial of the Nuremberg trials and Tuskegee syphilis experiment.
Values such as these do not give answers as to how to handle a particular situation, but provide a useful framework for understanding conflicts.
When moral values are in conflict, the result may be an ethical dilemma or crisis. Sometimes, no good solution to a dilemma in medical ethics exists, and occasionally, the values of the medical community (i.e., the hospital and its staff) conflict with the values of the individual patient, family, or larger non-medical community. Conflicts can also arise between health care providers, or among family members. Some argue for example, that the principles of autonomy and beneficence clash when patients refuse blood transfusions, considering them life-saving; and truth-telling was not emphasized to a large extent before the HIV era.

Confidentiality is commonly applied to conversations between doctors and patients. This concept is commonly known as patient-physician privilege.
Legal protections prevent physicians from revealing their discussions with patients, even under oath in court.
Confidentiality is mandated in America by HIPAA laws, specifically the Privacy Rule, and various state laws, some more rigorous than HIPAA. However, numerous exceptions to the rules have been carved out over the years. For example, many states require physicians to report gunshot wounds to the police and impaired drivers to the Department of Motor Vehicles. Confidentiality is also challenged in cases involving the diagnosis of a sexually transmitted disease in a patient who refuses to reveal the diagnosis to a spouse, and in the termination of a pregnancy in an underage patient, without the knowledge of the patient's parents. Many states in the U.S. have laws governing parental notification in underage abortion.
Traditionally, medical ethics has viewed the duty of confidentiality as a relatively non-negotiable tenet of medical practice. More recently, critics like Jacob Appel have argued for a more nuanced approach to the duty that acknowledges the need for flexibility in many cases.
Confidentiality is an important issue in primary care ethics, where physicians care for many patients from the same family and community, and where third parties often request information from the considerable medical database typically gathered in primary health care.

Often, simple communication is not enough to resolve a conflict, and a hospital ethics committee must convene to decide a complex matter.
These bodies are composed primarily of health care professionals, but may also include philosophers, lay people, and clergy - indeed, in many parts of the world their presence is considered mandatory in order to provide balance.
With respect to the expected composition of such bodies in the USA, Europe and Australia, the following applies .
U.S. recommendations suggest that Research and Ethical Boards (REBs) should have five or more members, including at least one scientist, one non-scientist and one person not affiliated with the institution. The REB should include people knowledgeable in the law and standards of practice and professional conduct. Special memberships are advocated for handicapped or disabled concerns, if required by the protocol under review. The European Forum for Good Clinical Practice (EFGCP) suggests that REBs include two practicing physicians who share experience in biomedical research and are independent from the institution where the research is conducted; one lay person; one lawyer; and one paramedical professional, e.g. nurse or pharmacist. They recommend that a quorum include both sexes from a wide age range and reflect the cultural make-up of the local community. The 1996 Australian Health Ethics Committee recommendations were entitled, "Membership Generally of Institutional Ethics Committees". They suggest a chairperson be preferably someone not employed or otherwise connected with the institution. Members should include a person with knowledge and experience in professional care, counselling or treatment of humans; a minister of religion or equivalent, e.g. Aboriginal elder; a layman; a laywoman; a lawyer and, in the case of a hospital-based ethics committee, a nurse.

The assignment of philosophers or religious clerics will reflect the importance attached by the society to the basic values involved.

Bioethics is the study of typically controversial ethics brought about by advances in biology and medicine. It is also moral discernment as it relates to medical policy, practice, and research. Bioethicists are concerned with the ethical questions that arise in the relationships among life sciences, biotechnology, medicine, politics, law, and philosophy. It also includes the study of the more commonplace questions of values ("the ethics of the ordinary") which arise in primary care and other branches of medicine.
The field of bioethics has addressed a broad swath of human inquiry, ranging from debates over the boundaries of life (e.g. abortion, euthanasia), surrogacy, the allocation of scarce health care resources (e.g. organ donation, health care rationing) to the right to refuse medical care for religious or cultural reasons. 

Bioethicists often disagree among themselves over the precise limits of their discipline, debating whether the field should concern itself with the ethical evaluation of all questions involving biology and medicine, or only a subset of these questions. Some bioethicists would narrow ethical evaluation only to the morality of medical treatments or technological innovations, and the timing of medical treatment of humans. Others would broaden the scope of ethical evaluation to include the morality of all actions that might help or harm organisms capable of feeling fear.

The scope of bioethics can expand with biotechnology, including cloning, gene therapy, life extension, human genetic engineering, astroethics and life in space, and manipulation of basic biology through altered DNA, XNA and proteins.These developments will affect future evolution, and may require new principles that address life at its core, such as biotic ethics that values life itself at its basic biological processes and structures, and seeks their propagation.

Historical cases

Historically, Western medical ethics may be traced to guidelines on the duty of physicians in antiquity, such as the Hippocratic Oath, and early Christian teachings. The first code of medical ethics, Formula Comitis Archiatrorum, was published in the 5th century, during the reign of the Ostrogothic king Theodoric the Great. In the medieval and early modern period, the field is indebted to Muslim medicine such as Ishaq ibn Ali al-Ruhawi (who wrote the Conduct of a Physician, the first book dedicated to medical ethics) and Muhammad ibn Zakariya ar-Razi (known as Rhazes in the West), Jewish thinkers such as Maimonides, Roman Catholic scholastic thinkers such as Thomas Aquinas, and the case-oriented analysis (casuistry) of Catholic moral theology. These intellectual traditions continue in Catholic, Islamic and Jewish medical ethics.

By the 18th and 19th centuries, medical ethics emerged as a more self-conscious discourse. In England, 
Thomas Percival, a physician and author, crafted the first modern code of medical ethics. He drew up a pamphlet with the code in 1794 and wrote an expanded version in 1803, in which he coined the expressions "medical ethics" and "medical jurisprudence".However, there are some who see Percival's guidelines that relate to physician consultations as being excessively protective of the home physician's reputation. Jeffrey Berlant is one such critic who considers Percival's codes of physician consultations as being an early example of the anti-competitive, "guild"-like nature of the physician community.

In 1815, the Apothecaries Act was passed by the Parliament of the United Kingdom. It introduced compulsory apprenticeship and formal qualifications for the apothecaries of the day under the license of the Society of Apothecaries. This was the beginning of regulation of the medical profession in the UK.
In 1847, the American Medical Association adopted its first code of ethics, with this being based in large part upon Percival's work. While the secularized field borrowed largely from Catholic medical ethics, in the 20th century a distinctively liberal Protestant approach was articulated by thinkers such as Joseph Fletcher. In the 1960s and 1970s, building upon liberal theory and procedural justice, much of the discourse of medical ethics went through a dramatic shift and largely reconfigured itself into bioethics.

Well-known medical ethics cases include:

Albert Kligman's dermatology experiments
Deep sleep therapy
Doctors' Trial
Henrietta Lacks
Human radiation experiments
Jesse Gelsinger
Moore v. Regents of the University of California
Surgical removal of body parts to try to improve mental health
Medical Experimentation on Black Americans
Milgram experiment
Radioactive iodine experiments
The Monster Study
Plutonium injections
The Stanford Prison Experiment
Tuskegee syphilis experiment
Willowbrook State School
Greenberg v. Miami Children's Hospital Research Institute
Since the 1970s, the growing influence of ethics in contemporary medicine can be seen in the increasing use of Institutional Review Boards to evaluate experiments on human subjects, the establishment of hospital ethics committees, the expansion of the role of clinician ethicists, and the integration of ethics into many medical school curricula.

Negligence

Medical malpractice (also known as medical negligence) is professional negligence by act or omission by a health care provider in which the treatment provided falls below the accepted standard of practice in the medical community and causes injury or death to the patient, with most cases involving medical error. Standards and regulations for medical malpractice vary by country and jurisdiction within countries. Medical professionals may obtain professional liability insurances to offset the risk and costs of lawsuits based on medical malpractice.
Negligence may be defined as the “breach of a duty caused by the omission to do  something which a reasonable man, guided by those considerations which ordinarily  regulate the conduct of human affairs would do, or doing something which a prudent and  reasonable man would not do”. A shorter definition is that “negligence as a tort is the  breach of legal duty to take care which results in damage, undesired by the defendant to  the plaintiff”. The definition involves three constituents of negligence: (1) A legal duty  to exercise the due care on the part of the party complained of towards the party  complaining the former’s conduct within the scope of the duty; (2) Breach of the said  duty; (3) consequential damage.

—In the leading case Bolam v. Friern Hospital Management Committee [(1957) 2 All
ER, wherein judge Mc Nair J. has stated as follows:
"………….. where you get a situation which involves the use of some special  skill or competence, then the test whether there has been negligence or not is not  the test of the man on the top of a Clapham omnibus, because he has not got this  special skill. The test is the standard of the ordinary skilled man exercising and  professing to have that special skill. A man need not possess the highest expert  skill at the risk of being found negligent. It is well-established law that it is  sufficient if he exercise the ordinary skill of an ordinary competent man  exercising that particular art. Counsel for the plaintiff put it in this way, that in  the case of a medical man, negligence means failure to act in accordance with the  standards of reasonably competent medical men at the time. That is a perfectly  accurate statement, as long as it is remembered that there may be one or more  perfectly proper standards; and if a medical man conforms with one of those  proper standards then he is not negligent. A doctor is not guilty of negligence if he  has acted in accordance with a practice accepted as proper by a responsible body  of medical men skilled in that particular art. Putting it the other way round, a  doctor is not negligent, if he is acting in accordance with such a practice, merely  because there is a body of opinion that takes a contrary view. At the same time,  that does not mean that a medical man can obstinately and pig-headedly carry on  with some old technique if it has been proved to be contrary to what is really  substantially the whole of informed medical opinion."

Informed consent

1.28 Informed Consent
A process by which a subject voluntarily confirms his or her willingness to participate in a particular trial, after having been informed of all aspects of the trial that are relevant to the subject's decision to participate. Informed consent is documented by means of a written, signed and dated informed consent form.

1.26 Impartial Witness
A person, who is independent of the trial, who cannot be unfairly influenced by people involved with the trial, who attends the informed consent process if the subject or the subject’s legally acceptable representative cannot read, and who reads the informed consent form and any other written information supplied to the subject.

1.27 Independent Ethics Committee (IEC)

An independent body (a review board or a committee, institutional, regional, national, or supranational), constituted of medical professionals and non-medical members, whose responsibility it is to ensure the protection of the rights, safety and well-being of human subjects involved in a trial and to provide public assurance of that protection, by, among other things, reviewing and approving / providing favourable opinion on, the trial protocol, the suitability of the investigator(s), facilities, and the methods and material to be used in obtaining and documenting informed consent of the trial subjects.
The legal status, composition, function, operations and regulatory requirements pertaining to Independent Ethics Committees may differ among countries, but should allow the Independent Ethics Committee to act in agreement with GCP as described in this guideline.

1.31 Institutional Review Board (IRB)
An independent body constituted of medical, scientific, and non-scientific members, whose responsibility is to ensure the protection of the rights, safety and well-being of human subjects involved in a trial by, among other things, reviewing, approving, and providing continuing review of trial protocol and amendments and of the methods and material to be used in obtaining and documenting informed consent of the trial subjects.

Freely given informed consent should be obtained from every subject prior to clinical trial participation.

The IRB/IEC should obtain the following documents:
trial protocol(s)/amendment(s), written informed consent form(s) and consent form updates that the investigator proposes for use in the trial, subject recruitment procedures (e.g. advertisements), written information to be provided to subjects, Investigator's Brochure (IB), available safety information, information about payments and compensation available to subjects, the investigator’s current curriculum vitae and/or other documentation evidencing qualifications, and any other documents that the IRB/IEC may need to fulfil its responsibilities.

The IRB/IEC should ensure that information regarding payment to subjects, including the methods, amounts, and schedule of payment to trial subjects, is set forth in the written informed consent form and any other written information to be provided to subjects. The way payment will be prorated should be specified.

Before initiating a trial, the investigator/institution should have written and dated approval/favourable opinion from the IRB/IEC for the trial protocol, written informed consent form, consent form updates, subject recruitment procedures (e.g., advertisements), and any other written information to be provided to subjects.

4.8 Informed Consent of Trial Subjects
4.8.1 In obtaining and documenting informed consent, the investigator should comply with the applicable regulatory requirement(s), and should adhere to GCP and to the ethical principles that have their origin in the Declaration of Helsinki. Prior to the beginning of the trial, the investigator should have the IRB/IEC's written approval/favourable opinion of the written informed consent form and any other written information to be provided to subjects.
4.8.2 The written informed consent form and any other written information to be provided to subjects should be revised whenever important new information becomes available that may be relevant to the subject’s consent. Any revised written informed consent form, and written information should receive the IRB/IEC's approval/favourable opinion in advance of use. The subject or the subject’s legally acceptable representative should be informed in a timely manner if new information becomes available that may be relevant to the subject’s willingness to continue participation in the trial. The communication of this information should be documented.

4.8.3 Neither the investigator, nor the trial staff, should coerce or unduly influence a subject to participate or to continue to participate in a trial.
4.8.4 None of the oral and written information concerning the trial, including the written informed consent form, should contain any language that causes the subject or the subject's legally acceptable representative to waive or to appear to waive any legal rights, or that releases or appears to release the investigator, the institution, the sponsor, or their agents from liability for negligence.
4.8.5 The investigator, or a person designated by the investigator, should fully inform the subject or, if the subject is unable to provide informed consent, the subject's legally acceptable representative, of all pertinent aspects of the trial including the written information and the approval/ favourable opinion by the IRB/IEC.
4.8.6 The language used in the oral and written information about the trial, including the written informed consent form, should be as non-technical as practical and should be understandable to the subject or the subject's legally acceptable representative and the impartial witness, where applicable.
4.8.7 Before informed consent may be obtained, the investigator, or a person designated by the investigator, should provide the subject or the subject's legally acceptable representative ample time and opportunity to inquire about details of the trial and to decide whether or not to participate in the trial. All questions about the trial should be answered to the satisfaction of the subject or the subject's legally acceptable representative.
4.8.8 Prior to a subject’s participation in the trial, the written informed consent form should be signed and personally dated by the subject or by the subject's legally

acceptable representative, and by the person who conducted the informed consent discussion.
4.8.9 If a subject is unable to read or if a legally acceptable representative is unable to read, an impartial witness should be present during the entire informed consent discussion. After the written informed consent form and any other written information to be provided to subjects, is read and explained to the subject or the subject’s legally acceptable representative, and after the subject or the subject’s legally acceptable representative has orally consented to the subject’s participation in the trial and, if capable of doing so, has signed and personally dated the informed consent form, the witness should sign and personally date the consent form. By signing the consent form, the witness attests that the information in the consent form and any other written information was accurately explained to, and apparently understood by, the subject or the subject's legally acceptable representative, and that informed consent was freely given by the subject or the subject’s legally acceptable representative.
4.8.10 Both the informed consent discussion and the written informed consent form and any other written information to be provided to subjects should include explanations of the following:
(a) That the trial involves research.
(b) The purpose of the trial.
(c) The trial treatment(s) and the probability for random assignment to each treatment.
(d) The trial procedures to be followed, including all invasive procedures.
(e) The subject's responsibilities.
(f) Those aspects of the trial that are experimental.
(g) The reasonably foreseeable risks or inconveniences to the subject and, when applicable, to an embryo, fetus, or nursing infant.
(h) The reasonably expected benefits. When there is no intended clinical benefit to the subject, the subject should be made aware of this.
(i) The alternative procedure(s) or course(s) of treatment that may be available to the subject, and their important potential benefits and risks.
(j) The compensation and/or treatment available to the subject in the event of trial-related injury.
(k) The anticipated prorated payment, if any, to the subject for participating in the trial.
(l) The anticipated expenses, if any, to the subject for participating in the trial.
(m) That the subject's participation in the trial is voluntary and that the subject may refuse to participate or withdraw from the trial, at any time, without penalty or loss of benefits to which the subject is otherwise entitled.
(n) That the monitor(s), the auditor(s), the IRB/IEC, and the regulatory authority(ies) will be granted direct access to the subject's original medical records for verification of clinical trial procedures and/or data, without violating the confidentiality of the subject, to the extent permitted by the applicable laws and regulations and that, by signing a written informed consent form, the subject or the subject's legally acceptable representative is authorizing such access.
(o) That records identifying the subject will be kept confidential and, to the extent permitted by the applicable laws and/or regulations, will not be made publicly available. If the results of the trial are published, the subject’s identity will remain confidential.
(p) That the subject or the subject's legally acceptable representative will be informed in a timely manner if information becomes available that may be relevant to the subject's willingness to continue participation in the trial.
(q) The person(s) to contact for further information regarding the trial and the rights of trial subjects, and whom to contact in the event of trial-related injury.
(r) The foreseeable circumstances and/or reasons under which the subject's participation in the trial may be terminated.
(s) The expected duration of the subject's participation in the trial.
(t) The approximate number of subjects involved in the trial.

4.8.11 Prior to participation in the trial, the subject or the subject's legally acceptable representative should receive a copy of the signed and dated written informed consent form and any other written information provided to the subjects. During a subject’s participation in the trial, the subject or the subject’s legally acceptable representative should receive a copy of the signed and dated consent form updates and a copy of any amendments to the written information provided to subjects.
4.8.12 When a clinical trial (therapeutic or non-therapeutic) includes subjects who can only be enrolled in the trial with the consent of the subject’s legally acceptable representative (e.g., minors, or patients with severe dementia), the subject should be informed about the trial to the extent compatible with the subject’s understanding and, if capable, the subject should sign and personally date the written informed consent.
4.8.13 Except as described in 4.8.14, a non-therapeutic trial (i.e. a trial in which there is no anticipated direct clinical benefit to the subject), should be conducted in subjects who personally give consent and who sign and date the written informed consent form.
4.8.14 Non-therapeutic trials may be conducted in subjects with consent of a legally acceptable representative provided the following conditions are fulfilled:
(a) The objectives of the trial can not be met by means of a trial in subjects who can give informed consent personally.
(b) The foreseeable risks to the subjects are low.
(c) The negative impact on the subject’s well-being is minimized and low.
(d) The trial is not prohibited by law.
(e) The approval/favourable opinion of the IRB/IEC is expressly sought on the inclusion of such  subjects, and the written approval/ favourable opinion covers this aspect.

Such trials, unless an exception is justified, should be conducted in patients having a disease or condition for which the investigational product is intended. Subjects in these trials should be particularly closely monitored and should be withdrawn if they appear to be unduly distressed.
4.8.15 In emergency situations, when prior consent of the subject is not possible, the consent of the subject's legally acceptable representative, if present, should be requested. When prior consent of the subject is not possible, and the subject’s legally acceptable representative is not available, enrolment of the subject should require measures described in the protocol and/or elsewhere, with documented approval/favourable opinion by the IRB/IEC, to protect the rights, safety and well-being of the subject and to ensure compliance with applicable regulatory requirements. The subject or the subject's legally acceptable representative should be informed about the trial as soon as possible and consent to continue and other consent as appropriate (see 4.8.10) should be requested.

Mental competence Up – to – date cases


A simple guide to the Mental Capacity Act 2005 in relation to research
1               Summary
From 1 October 2007, research covered by the Act cannot include any people who lack capacity to consent to the research unless:
  • The research has the approval of a research ethics committee recognised by either the Secretary of State or the Welsh Assembly Government, as appropriate
  • The researcher considers the views of carers and other relevant people
  • The research treats the person’s interests as more important than those of science and society, and
  • The researcher respects any advance decisions or expressed preferences of a person who lacks capacity and any objections the person makes during the research

1.1         Timetable
The provisions of sections 30-33 of the Act came into force on 1 October 2007. Any new research starting on or after 1 October 2007 must have section 30 approval from an NHS REC and comply fully with the provisions of sections 30-33 if it is “intrusive research” involving one or more adults unable to consent for themselves.

Research starting prior to 1 October 2007 is not required to comply with sections 30-33 until 1 October 2008, provided it has ethical approval. Where the research is still underway on 1 October 2008, it must have section 30 approval from an NHS REC by that date.

2               Remit of the Act
The Mental Capacity Act is relevant to research involving adults over the age of 16 in England and Wales, except Clinical Trials of Investigational Medicinal Products (CTIMPs) - the Medicines for Human Use (Clinical Trials) Regulations 2004 make legal provision for participation in CTIMPs by adults lacking capacity to consent. In Scotland the Adults with Incapacity (Scotland) Act 2000 applies. There is no specific legislation in Northern Ireland. The parts of the Mental Capacity Act that are relevant to research came into force on 1 October 2007.

The Mental Capacity Act provides the legal arrangements to enable adults lacking capacity to consent to take part in research other than CTIMPs (including health and social care research) that would otherwise require the participant’s consent. The Mental Capacity Act also enables adults with capacity to make arrangements or make their wishes known in advance, to deal with future situations where they lack capacity to consent to take part in research.


3               What is mental capacity?
Mental capacity is the ability to make a decision. Capacity can only be assessed in relation to a particular decision and a particular time – a person may have the capacity to make some decisions but not others, or the capacity may vary over time.

3.1         The two-stage test of capacity
·         Is there an impairment of, or disturbance in, the functioning of the person’s mind or brain?
                        If so:
·         Is the impairment or disturbance sufficient to cause the person to be unable to make that particular decision at the relevant time?

Lack of capacity can be due to a range of causes, including unconsciousness, dementia, learning disabilities, stroke, head injuries or mental health problems.

Under the Mental Capacity Act, the following factors have to be considered when assessing if someone has capacity to make a decision:
  • whether they are able to understand the information
  • whether they are able to retain the information related to the decision to be made
  • whether they are able to use or weigh that information as part of the process of making the decision
  • whether they are able to communicate that decision – by any means, including blinking an eye or squeezing a hand.

3.2         The five core principles
1        A person must be assumed to have capacity unless it is established that they lack capacity.
2        A person is not to be treated as unable to make a decision unless all practicable (doable) steps to help them to do so have been taken without success.
3        A person is not to be treated as unable to make a decision merely because they make an unwise decision.
4        An act done, or decision made, under this Act for or on behalf of a person who lacks capacity must be done, or made, in their best interests.
5        Before the act is done, or the decision is made, regard must be had to whether the purpose for which it is needed can be as effectively achieved in a way that is less restrictive of the person’s rights and freedom of action.

4               Mental Capacity and Research (Sections 30 – 34)
4.1         Ethical approval (Sections 30 - 31)
Any research involving, or in relation to, a person lacking capacity that would otherwise have required consent from participants may only be lawfully carried out if an NHS research ethics committee (REC) in England or Wales has given a favourable opinion. This requirement includes research that would otherwise fall outside the remit of an NHS REC. The REC can only approve the research if it meets the following criteria:
  • the research must relate to the condition causing the mind or brain impairment, or to a condition resulting from or attributed to the mind or brain impairment;
  • the research cannot be done as effectively using people who have mental capacity; and
  • the research must produce results relevant to the condition (or a similar condition) affecting the person and have small risks or low adverse impact on the person, or it must have potential benefits to the person without disproportionate risk.
The researcher must stop the research if at any time they think that one of the above criteria is not met at any time during the research, unless withdrawal of any treatment as part of the research would impose a significant health risk.



4.2         Identifying a consultee (Section 32 - 33)
Where an adult lacks capacity to consent to take part in research, a consultee should be consulted. A personal consultee may be a family member, carer, or attorney acting under a Legal Power of Attorney, as long as they are not paid to look after the person in question and their interest in the welfare of the person is not a professional one. If they say that the person who lacks capacity would not have wanted to take part, or to continue to take part, then this means that the research must not go ahead.

If there is no such personal consultee who can be consulted, the researcher must find someone who is not connected with the research who can fulfil this role instead – a nominated consultee. Where the research relates to serious medical treatment, the consultee could be an independent mental capacity advocate. Again, if the consultee says that the person would not have wanted to take part or continue to take part, the research must not go ahead.

The researcher must provide the consultee with information about the research, and ask for advice on whether the person should take part in the research, and what the person’s wishes would be likely to be if they had capacity.

If the person shows any signs of resistance or indicates in any way that he or she does not wish to take part, the person must be withdrawn from the project immediately, unless withdrawal of any treatment as part of the research would impose a significant health risk.

In an emergency, if it is not possible to consult with a consultee in sufficient time, then the researcher must obtain agreement from an independent registered medical practitioner or comply with any other requirement of the REC.

Guidance on nominating a consultee for research involving adults who lack capacity to consent has been published by the Department of Health (see section 10). The sponsor or organisation providing care should have a local policy on the selection and training of the nominated consultees for research taking place within that organisation.

4.3         Loss of capacity during research (Section 34)
Where research started before the Act came into force (1 October 2007) and a person originally had capacity to consent and gave consent before 31 March 2008, research involving tissue or data collected from that person before a loss of capacity may continue if the participant later loses capacity before the end of the project. This research is permitted under the Loss of Capacity Regulations. Such research must have procedures for dealing with people who lose capacity during the project that have been approved by the research ethics committee. Approval for the procedures should be made by submitting a substantial amendment. However, the research does not need to meet the criteria in section 4.1. When a person loses capacity during a project, the researcher must seek the views of a consultee and act in the best interests of the person.

4.4         Research involving human tissue
The Mental Capacity Act permits the removal of tissue from a person lacking capacity, if it is in their best interests. The tissue can be stored or used for research if:
·         The research is to get information relevant to the health of another individual, and in the best interests of the person who lacks capacity;
·         The research is a clinical trial of an investigational medicinal product; or
·         The research is carried out under the Mental Capacity Act, meets the Acts requirements and has ethical approval

4.5         Transitional arrangements for research started before 1 October 2007
Research that started before the Mental Capacity Act came into force and involving participants who did not have capacity to consent when they entered the study, must obtain approval from a relevant REC in order to continue under the Act after 1 October 2008. Application for approval should be made by 1 April 2008. Such research must meet the requirements of the Mental Capacity Act.

4.6         Research not covered by the Mental Capacity Act
Clinical trials of investigational medicinal products are not covered by the Mental Capacity Act because arrangements for participation of adults lacking in capacity are covered by separate legislation. Other research that does not require consent does not require specific arrangements for adults lacking capacity. This includes research involving only:
·         anonymised data;
·         anonymised human tissue obtained from the living;
·         human tissue collected prior to 31 August 2006; or
·         confidential patient information used under approval of the Secretary of State through the Patient Information Advisory Group (PIAG).

5               Best interests decisions and acts
The Mental Capacity Act requires any decision or act made on behalf of a person who lacks capacity to be made in that person’s best interests. The interests of the person must be assumed to outweigh those of science and society. The Act does not define best interests but anyone making such a decision should take into account:
  • The persons’ past and present wishes and feelings, including any advance decisions
  • The beliefs and values that would be likely to affect their decision if they had capacity
  • Other factors that the person might have considered if they were able to do so.

6               Lasting Power of Attorney
Under a Lasting Power of Attorney (LPA) an individual can, while they still have capacity, appoint another person to make decisions on their behalf. They can give power to the attorney to make all decisions or they can choose which decisions they can make. When acting under an LPA, an attorney has the authority to make decisions on behalf of the person who made it if they can no longer make these decisions for themselves. In these cases, an attorney is not there simply to be consulted (although they should still be consulted if appropriate where other decisions are being made). Attorneys must act in accordance with the Code of Practice.

7               Advance decisions
An advance decision to refuse treatment enables an adult to make treatment decisions in the event of their losing their capacity at some time in the future.

8               Independent mental capacity advocates
The Mental Capacity Act introduces a duty on the NHS to involve an independent mental capacity advocate (IMCA) in decisions about serious medical treatment, when a person who lacks capacity to make a decision has no one who can speak for them. An IMCA is not a decision maker for the person who lacks capacity. They are there to support and represent that person and to ensure that decision making for people who lack capacity is done appropriately and in accordance with the Act.

9               Children and young people
The Mental Capacity Act does not usually apply to children younger than 16 who do not have capacity. Generally, people with parental responsibility for such children can make decisions on their behalf under common law. For 16 or 17-year-olds who lacks capacity to consent, the person providing care or treatment must follow the Act’s principles and act in a way that they reasonably believe to be in the young person’s best interests. Parents, others with parental responsibility, or anyone else involved in the care of the young person should be consulted unless the young person does not want this or this would otherwise breach their right to confidentiality. Any known views of the young person should also be taken into account.

 (Ref: www.rdforum.nhs.uk/docs/mca_guidance.doc)

  
Cloning

Introduction

In early 1997, a research team in Scotland cloned a sheep, Dolly, by modifying technology developed some decades previously with amphibians. Then, in July of 1998, researchers at the University of Hawaii produced mouse clones and developed a process by which mass cloning could occur. The technique used in both cases, somatic cell nuclear transfer, involves taking a nucleus from a somatic cell, placing it in an enucleated ovum, and implanting the ovum into a host uterus.
The cloning of Dolly brought to the forefront a longstanding debate about cloning human beings. The National Bioethics Advisory Commission recommended a five-year moratorium on any attempts to create a child through somatic cell nuclear transfer in the United States and urged the President to work with all other nations to do the same With the moratorium in place in the United States, legislative attempts to exercise permanent control over human cloning, such as the federal “Prohibition of Cloning of Human Beings Act of 1998,” have been introduced in Congress.
Human cloning is a matter for the medical profession’s attention since it would involve medical procedures and technology, and it may result in the creation of new genetic and psychological conditions that would require professional care. Therefore, the medical profession must evaluate the ethics of human cloning, and in particular, the potential role of physicians in the practice. The Council’s purpose here is to consider whether physicians should participate in human cloning, not to determine whether it should be legal or illegal.
The Council on Ethical and Judicial Affairs offers the following report to assess the ethical uncertainties involved in human cloning. It will address what are currently perceived to be the most widely discussed applications of human cloning, and it will lay the groundwork for future reports. Issues involving embryo research, stem cell research, embryo splitting, embryo twinning, and embryo donor organisms will be addressed in future reports. A scientific analysis of cloning technology can be found in a companion report issued by the Council on Scientific Affairs.
Definitions
For the purposes of this report, the term “cloning” will refer to the production of genetically identical organisms via somatic cell nuclear transfer.ii “Somatic cell nuclear transfer” refers to the process in which the nucleus of a somatic cell of an existing (or previously existing) organism is transferred into an oocyte from which the nucleus has been removed. “Human cloning” will be used to refer to the application of somatic nuclear transfer technology to the creation of a human being that shares all of its nuclear genes with the person donating the implanted nucleus.
Cloning is distinct from techniques such as embryo splitting and twinning. Human cloning, as defined in this report, does not include the use of somatic cells to create a pluripotent cell line that could, for instance, also be used for extra-uterine production of transplantable tissues without the creation of an entire being. Nor does it include the use of cloning technology for the production of human tissues or human proteins from transgenic mammals.

Existing Limits on Human Cloning
Coverage of advances in cloning, especially in the popular press, has described the prospects of manufacturing armies of programmed killers, duplicating sports stars or academic geniuses, and recreating deceased loved ones.iii Based on the intrinsic limitations of human cloning technology, some widely mentioned undesirable applications of cloning are impossible, and others, which may be possible technically, are clearly prohibited by existing law, public policy, and professional ethical standards. The following sections describe these issues in more detail. In order to clarify the many misconceptions about human cloning, physicians should help educate the public about the intrinsic technical limits of human cloning as well as the ethical and legal protections that should prevent abuses of human cloning.
A. Replicating specific persons
The term “cloning” may suggest that one organism is the exact replica of another. Human clones would be identical insofar as they would have the same nuclear genes as the donor. However, as observed in natural monozygotic twins, having identical genes does not result in two indistinguishable individuals. A clone must— because of the different environment and circumstances in which he or she creates his or her life story— be a different person from the person from whom he or she was cloned. Although human cloning may be thought of as a sort of “delayed twinning,” twins may be more similar than clones since most twins are conceived and nurtured in the same environment in utero and often during childhood.
Since environment has a profound influence on development, human clones likely would be different in terms of personality and other characteristics. Because cloning would not produce exact replicas, several applications of human cloning are illogical. In particular, human cloning would not be a solution to terminal illness or mortality. Children are already thought of as a way to “soften the blow of mortality,” and clones may be seen as a more powerful approach since there is no sharing or mixing of genomes.iv The possibility of having one’s life to live over again, or of getting back a lost child, might be attractive. But the clone would not be the same person as the cloned individual. The fact remains that the person does die and cannot be replaced.
The same reasoning applies to recreating sports stars, dictators, and geniuses— genetics does not wholly define a person. Cloning may allow the persistence of certain genotypes and derived phenotypic traits, but it does not provide individual immortality or replication. A clone of a sports star will not necessarily be a superb athlete, and even if he or she did possess keen athletic ability, he or she would not be identical to the cloned sports star. However, the idea that the clone’s life choices would be affected by other’s expectations raises additional disturbing possibilities that are addressed below.

B. Creating clones without consent
There is some concern that human clones would be developed from cells obtained without one’s permission since, unlike traditional procreative methods, isolated somatic cells potentially could yield clones. If this technique becomes a possibility, the moral foundations of the therapeutic relationship would have to apply. These include trust, personal respect, and the healer’s fiduciary obligation to serve the patient’s health interests. Any attempt to clone a patient involuntarily would violate all three of these fundamental precepts of medical ethics.
In addition, the doctrine of informed consent would have to apply if this technique becomes a possibility. In Opinion 8.08, “Informed Consent,” the Council has recognized that “the patient should make his or her own determination on treatment.”  This includes procedures for reproduction. Few exceptions exist to this basic social policy. In addition to ethical safeguards, there are legal protections against procreation without consent. Cloning a patient involuntarily would likely violate the patient’s existing constitutional rights to privacy and reproductive freedom.vi Therefore, under no circumstances should cloning occur without an individual’s permission.
C. Respecting the rights of clones
Many of the other unrealistic applications of human cloning, such as creating armies of clones or creating human organ factories, stems from the underlying fear that clones would be denied the same rights as other individuals in society. Children are entitled to the same protections as every other individual in society. The fact that a human clone’s nuclear genes would derive from a single individual rather than two parents does not change its moral standing. This standard should be applied to every supposed use of clones.

The Realistic Uses of Human Cloning
A. Assisted Reproduction

There are some realistic applications for cloning technology in the medical arena. One of the most likely uses is as a method of assisted reproduction. To the benefit of many patients, the widespread introduction of assisted reproductive technologies has resulted in a great number of pregnancies and births that otherwise could not have occurred. The use of in-vitro methods of fertilization, donor eggs, donor sperm, and/or surrogate mothers have proved to be effective treatments for infertility. Assisted reproductive technologies are also attractive options to individuals or couples who do not choose to reproduce by traditional means. Cloning technology might allow any couple or individual to reproduce with minimal genetic input from another party.

Because of the prevalence of assisted reproductive technologies and the rapid rate of technological development in this arena, cloning rarely would be the only reproductive option available to prospective parents. For example, scientists recently have pioneered a technique in which DNA is transferred from an infertile woman’s oocyte to a viable donor oocyte.vii In addition, the development of somatic cell gene therapy and other technologies may allow for the treatment of genetic disorders— an alternative to avoiding all genetic contribution from a partner with a disease gene. One issue for this report is whether it would be justifiable to make cloning available to individuals who could use existing or alternative options.

Many of the issues that arise in the context of cloning, for example with respect to medical, psychological, or social harms, can be compared to issues that arise in the use of other assisted reproductive techniques. Generally speaking, the medical profession should be satisfied that the benefits of commonly used reproductive interventions outweigh the risks to individuals, families, and their offspring enough to justify medical cooperation with informed patient requests for these services. Evaluating whether or not this calculus has been done for all of the currently used reproductive technologies is beyond the scope of this report. Regardless, cloning should be subject to such a balancing.

In considering cloning as another reproductive health tool, the profession should evaluate whether the ethical concerns introduced by assisted reproductive technologies will be exacerbated in the case of cloning to the point where they outweigh potential benefits to individuals, families, and their offspring. For example, human cloning appears to represent a significant step toward turning children into “products of human will and design,” a situation that many find problematic.viii Determining the balance of possible harms and benefits will require further investigation and discussion regarding human cloning with consideration given to the points raised in the next section.

Individuals do not have a right to demand that physicians participate in human cloning. Before physicians would be justified in participating in human cloning, the harms and benefits need to be evaluated further with some of the issues requiring discussion on a societal level. Until these issues are brought closer to resolution and benefits clearly outweigh harms, it would be inappropriate for physicians to participate in human cloning. Cloning technology also potentially may be used to create a person with tissues immunologically matched to an existing individual. If the technology uses somatic nuclear transfer for cell or tissue production without creating a human being, then this is not human cloning by the definition used here. One scenario that has been discussed in the context of human cloning is the possibility of manufacturing “donor organisms.” In this context, donor organisms are humans in early stages of development created for the sole purpose of harvesting their organs.ix The creation of human embryo or fetal donor organisms will be addressed in a future report.

Legal and ethical protections already preclude the use of cloned children as discardable donor organisms. Medical ethics is grounded in the principle of nonmaleficence, or the avoidance of harm. Any involvement by a physician in the deliberate sacrifice or harm of children in order to harvest organs would violate this axiom. Further, this practice would be considered murder. Even where the clone would not be destroyed, the ethical prohibition against using human beings merely as means rather than as ends in themselves makes the possibility of using human cloning to create an organ donor controversial. Nevertheless, even without human cloning, the practice of having children in order to create matching tissue for an older sibling already occurs. One couple unable to find a matching donor for their first child’s bone marrow transplant decided to have a second child on the chance that he or she would also have the rare marrow type. Notably, the couple indicated that they had wanted another child and that they would care for the resulting child irrespective of his or her marrow type. In this situation, hoping the child had the same marrow type as its sibling did not preclude the couple from valuing the child for its own sake. xi A cloned person, however, would be born with assurance of tissue compatibility, and perhaps with the expectation of tissue donation.

There are limits on the types of procedures to which parents can consent. In a previous report, “The Use of Minors as Organ and Tissue Donors,” the Council has described the standards that proxies should use when making a decision to donate a minor’s organs.xii One of the standards the Council recommends is a “best interests test” based on the principles of beneficence and nonmaleficence in which the proxy “attempts to ascertain what would bring the most good to the person… and at the very least… do no harm to that person.” Physicians can help parents with the calculus of determining the best interest of the child.
Technological advances in organ and tissue research might alleviate the need to develop a human being in order to produce a matching organ. For example, somatic cell nuclear transfer may be used to produce only the matching, transplantable tissues. Improved pharmaceutical interventions to lower the rate of organ and tissue rejection could also reduce the need for tissue compatibility

Ethical Concerns Regarding Human Cloning

Physicians have an ethical obligation to consider the harms and benefits of new medical procedures and technologies. In weighing the harms and benefits, physicians should consider the possible implications of human cloning. Potential physical harms, psychosocial harms, adverse effects on familial relations, and changes to the gene pool are all legitimate issues. Compared to other technologies that might be used to address reproductive limitations and organ and tissue shortages, these potential harms of human cloning appear to outweigh the potential benefits at this time.


A. Physical harms introduced by cloning

While the Council will address the harms and benefits of embryo research in a future report, it is important to note that techniques used for cloning humans could potentially endanger the developing individuals. The Human Embryo Research Panel of the National Institutes of Health (NIH), in its 1994 study, advised that embryos should be transferred to a woman’s uterus only when “there is reasonable confidence that any child born as a result” will not be harmed.xiii At present, this cannot be assured with any degree of certainty with human cloning. Somatic cell nuclear transfer has not yet been refined and its long-term safety has not yet been proven. The possibility of genetic or cellular conditions, and perhaps an array of illnesses associated with cloning, is of great concern. While the demise of countless amphibian, lamb, and mouse fetuses may be disturbing, similar wastage and mortality among human fetuses is unacceptable. Moreover, we might have significant concerns about offering such technology to women as a mechanism to facilitate reproduction given the potential harms from the expected high miscarriage rate. The risk of producing individuals with developmental anomalies is serious and precludes human cloning for the time being. Producing disabled human clones would give rise to an obligation to seek better understanding of— and potential medical therapies for— the unforeseen consequences that could arise from human cloning.

B. Psychosocial harms introduced by cloning

Human cloning has the potential to introduce psychosocial harms to individuals. If a person with known genetic predispositions and conditions is cloned, the cloned child’s genetic predispositions and conditions will, due to the very nature of cloning, also be known to a certain extent. For the most part, environment will also play a significant role. Presently, a child’s genetic predispositions can be predicted to varying degrees if the parent’s genetic predispositions have been determined. Knowledge of a child’s genetic predispositions raises concerns about the autonomy and best interests of the child. The Council has urged caution in this area in its ethical Opinion 2.138, “Genetic Testing of Children.”  Knowledge of genetic information holds great significance to an individual. The harm of preempting the child’s future choice in knowing or forgoing knowledge of his genetic status and the danger of abrogating the child’s right to privacy with respect to this status must be weighed carefully.

Foregoing choice in learning one’s genetic predispositions may seem trivial compared to the concerns about identity raised with human cloning. If raised by the clone-parent, a clone-child could see what he or she has the potential to become. In this respect, human clones would differ dramatically from monozygotic twins who develop simultaneously. The timing of development is a key difference between monozygotic twins and human clones. Having insight into one’s potential may cause enormous pressures to live up to expectations (or inappropriately relieve pressure to do so), even more so than those generally experienced by children.
Presumably, a person would clone him or herself or another individual because that person has desirable characteristics that would be reflected in the clone. For example, the person who cloned a sports star presumably would hope that the clone-child develops into another sports star. A sports star’s clone-child unable to live up to these expectations could be dubbed a failure unable to capitalize on his or her genetic gift. Moreover, although the clone-child of a sports star might feel more confident of his or her abilities from the outset, other clone-children may feel limited by their genetic lot. If a clone-child saw that he or she was likely to develop certain diseases or had failed at certain tasks, his or her undertakings might be bounded by what the clone-parent had done. Therefore, cloning might limit the clone-child’s perception of self and increase external pressures. Human cloning may diminish, at least psychologically, the seemingly unlimited potential of new human beings and may exacerbate disturbing motivations for having children.

C. The impact of human cloning on family and society

In addition to concerns about individual privacy and identity, the implications of cloning for family and broader social relationships remain uncharted. What would be the consequence to, say, the fatherdaughter relationship if the daughter and wife were genetically identical? Would a woman have a normal mother-daughter relationship with her clone?xv These examples illustrate that the family unit might be quite different with the introduction of cloning. As one philosopher wrote: “cloning shows itself to be a major violation of our given nature as embodied, gendered, and engendering beings— and of the social relations built on this natural ground.” Additionally, some problems are technical and legal in nature. For instance, birth cousins could be genetic siblings, and this might result in a need to revisit laws governing marital eligibility. Also, the courts have had difficulty sorting out parental rights in cases of assisted reproduction. In one case, a court found a child conceived using assisted reproductive technologies to have no parents despite having eight individuals from which to choose.
While discussion and resolution of these issues is not the province of physicians, the impact of human cloning on family and society is an important factor for physicians to consider when weighing the costs and benefits of cloning. Until more thought is given on a societal level regarding how to construct familial relations in this context, physicians should not participate in human cloning.

D. The effects of human cloning on the gene pool

Although not the most imminent threat, human cloning has the potential to alter the gene pool. In order for human cloning to have a significant effect on the gene pool, cloning would have to be widespread, and clones would have to reproduce. If cloning became widespread, human genetic diversity would decrease. Over time, the benefits of genetic diversity, from having individuals with disease immunity to fostering a population with a wide variety of talents, have helped human beings survive and succeed. Like other interventions that can change individuals’ reproductive patterns and the resulting genetic characteristics of a population, human cloning raises the specter of eugenics.The possibility that physicians might play a part in deciding which persons are or are not “worthy” of cloning is contrary to professional medical values by all respectable accounts. For the most part, those individuals thought to possess desirable characteristics or lack undesirable ones would be cloned. In addition, as is the worry with many assisted reproductive technologies, only those who have the ability to pay or are members of favored social groups will have access. This would have the potential to skew the gene pool in the direction of favored social groups and whatever characteristics are thought to be advantageous at the time, even though the long-term desirability of the characteristics is unknown. The possibility that physicians might be the agents of a social policy that make such judgments is contrary to professional medical values. The application of cloning for eugenic or discriminatory practices is incompatible with the ethical norms of medical practice.

In addition, since the somatic cell from which clones originate likely will have acquired mutations, serial cloning would compound the accumulation of mutations that occur in somatic cells. Although these mutations might not be apparent at the time of cloning, genetic problems could become exacerbated in future generations. These possibilities need to be investigated further before physicians participate in human cloning.

The Need for International Regulations

Even if the United States developed sound ethical guidelines and well-crafted regulations to address the practice of human cloning, some fear that human cloning would simply be forced into other locales. Individuals could travel to other countries where human cloning would be available and potentially unregulated. Because cloning technology is not limited to the United States, physicians should help establish international guidelines regarding human cloning.



Human embryos and IVF Shared responsibilities for decisions and the understanding of risk


At first glance, the case for federal funding of embryonic stem-cell research seems too obvious to need defending. Why should the government refuse to support research that holds promise for the treatment and cure of devastating conditions such as Parkinson's disease, Alzheimer's disease, diabetes, and spinal cord injury? Critics of stem-cell research offer two main objections: some hold that despite its worthy ends, stem-cell research is wrong because it involves the destruction of human embryos; others worry that even if research on embryos is not wrong in itself, it will open the way to a slippery slope of dehumanizing practices, such as embryo farms, cloned babies, the use of fetuses for spare parts, and the commodification of human life.

Neither objection is ultimately persuasive, though each raises questions that proponents of stem-cell research should take seriously. Consider the first objection. Those who make it begin by arguing, rightly, that biomedical ethics is not only about ends but also about means; even research that achieves great good is unjustified if it comes at the price of violating fundamental human rights. For example, the ghoulish experiments of Nazi doctors would not be morally justified even if they resulted in discoveries that alleviated human suffering.

Few would dispute the idea that respect for human dignity imposes certain moral constraints on medical research. The question is whether the destruction of human embryos in stem-cell research amounts to the killing of human beings. The “embryo objection” insists that it does. For those who adhere to this view, extracting stem cells from a blastocyst is morally equivalent to yanking organs from a baby to save other people's lives.

Some base this conclusion on the religious belief that ensoulment occurs at conception. Others try to defend it without recourse to religion, by the following line of reasoning: Each of us began life as an embryo. If our lives are worthy of respect, and hence inviolable, simply by virtue of our humanity, one would be mistaken to think that at some younger age or earlier stage of development we were not worthy of respect. Unless we can point to a definitive moment in the passage from conception to birth that marks the emergence of the human person, this argument claims, we must regard embryos as possessing the same inviolability as fully developed human beings.
But this argument is flawed. The fact that every person began life as an embryo does not prove that embryos are persons. Consider an analogy: although every oak tree was once an acorn, it does not follow that acorns are oak trees, or that I should treat the loss of an acorn eaten by a squirrel in my front yard as the same kind of loss as the death of an oak tree felled by a storm. Despite their developmental continuity, acorns and oak trees are different kinds of things. So are human embryos and human beings. Sentient creatures make claims on us that nonsentient ones do not; beings capable of experience and consciousness make higher claims still. Human life develops by degrees.

Those who view embryos as persons often assume that the only alternative is to treat them with moral indifference. But one need not regard the embryo as a full human being in order to accord it a certain respect. To regard an embryo as a mere thing, open to any use we desire or devise, does, it seems to me, miss its significance as potential human life. Few would favor the wanton destruction of embryos or the use of embryos for the purpose of developing a new line of cosmetics. Personhood is not the only warrant for respect. For example, we consider it an act of disrespect when a hiker carves his initials in an ancient sequoia — not because we regard the sequoia as a person, but because we regard it as a natural wonder worthy of appreciation and awe. To respect the old-growth forest does not mean that no tree may ever be felled or harvested for human purposes. Respecting the forest may be consistent with using it. But the purposes should be weighty and appropriate to the wondrous nature of the thing.

The notion that an embryo in a petri dish has the same moral status as a person can be challenged on further grounds. Perhaps the best way to see its implausibility is to play out its full implications. First, if harvesting stem cells from a blastocyst were truly on a par with harvesting organs from a baby, then the morally responsible policy would be to ban it, not merely deny it federal funding. If some doctors made a practice of killing children to get organs for transplantation, no one would take the position that the infanticide should be ineligible for federal funding but allowed to continue in the private sector. If we were persuaded that embryonic stem-cell research were tantamount to infanticide, we would not only ban it but treat it as a grisly form of murder and subject scientists who performed it to criminal punishment.

Second, viewing the embryo as a person rules out not only stem-cell research, but all fertility treatments that involve the creation and discarding of excess embryos. In order to increase pregnancy rates and spare women the ordeal of repeated attempts, most in vitro fertilization clinics create more fertilized eggs than are ultimately implanted. Excess embryos are typically frozen indefinitely or discarded. (A small number are donated for stem-cell research.) But if it is immoral to sacrifice embryos for the sake of curing or treating devastating diseases, it is also immoral to sacrifice them for the sake of treating infertility.

Third, defenders of in vitro fertilization point out that embryo loss in assisted reproduction is less frequent than in natural pregnancy, in which more than half of all fertilized eggs either fail to implant or are otherwise lost. This fact highlights a further difficulty with the view that equates embryos and persons. If natural procreation entails the loss of some embryos for every successful birth, perhaps we should worry less about the loss of embryos that occurs in in vitro fertilization and stem-cell research. Those who view embryos as persons might reply that high infant mortality would not justify infanticide. But the way we respond to the natural loss of embryos suggests that we do not regard this event as the moral or religious equivalent of the death of infants. Even those religious traditions that are the most solicitous of nascent human life do not mandate the same burial rituals and mourning rites for the loss of an embryo as for the death of a child. Moreover, if the embryo loss that accompanies natural procreation were the moral equivalent of infant death, then pregnancy would have to be regarded as a public health crisis of epidemic proportions; alleviating natural embryo loss would be a more urgent moral cause than abortion, in vitro fertilization, and stem-cell research combined.

Even critics of stem-cell research hesitate to embrace the full implications of the embryo objection. President George W. Bush has prohibited federal funding for research on embryonic stem-cell lines derived after August 9, 2001, but has not sought to ban such research, nor has he called on scientists to desist from it. And as the stem-cell debate heats up in Congress, even outspoken opponents of embryo research have not mounted a national campaign to ban in vitro fertilization or to prohibit fertility clinics from creating and discarding excess embryos. This does not mean that their positions are unprincipled — only that their positions cannot rest on the principle that embryos are inviolable.

What else could justify restricting federal funding for stem-cell research? It might be the worry, mentioned above, that embryo research will lead down a slippery slope of exploitation and abuse. This objection raises legitimate concerns, but curtailing stem-cell research is the wrong way to address them. Congress can stave off the slippery slope by enacting sensible regulations, beginning with a simple ban on human reproductive cloning. Following the approach adopted by the United Kingdom, Congress might also require that research embryos not be allowed to develop beyond 14 days, restrict the commodification of embryos and gametes, and establish a stem-cell bank to prevent proprietary interests from monopolizing access to stem-cell lines. Regulations such as these could save us from slouching toward a brave new world as we seek to redeem the great biomedical promise of our time.



The issue of IVF treatments and the supposed “right to a child” raises some complex ethical issues. Compare these two comments: "Being denied appropriate fertility treatment can have a devastating consequence on patients’ lives, effectively denying them the right to a family." (Dr Sue Avery of British Fertility Society). Dr Andrew Davies, chair of Warrington Health Consortium, said: "While we fully understand infertility is a condition that causes great distress to couples, it does not affect general physical health or life expectancy." Here are the main points to consider: (click read more below)

1. Issues of what a “right to a family” actually means. Arguably you cannot have a “right” unless someone else has an obligation to protect and uphold that right. There is no right to free speech if you never allow me to speak, so in the case of IVF treatments, who is obliged to provide that treatment? If it is the taxpayer who pays for it, then should the taxpayer be required to pay for every woman below a certain age to have this treatment?

2. Issues of which family unit qualifies. At present every woman applying for NHS treatment is screened by the ethics committee of the local hospital trust. Occasionally women are denied treatment as “unsuitable”. But what of gay couples? Should they have the absolute right to a surrogate child? Should they have exactly parallel rights to heterosexual couples?

3. Issues of justice. It depends where you live how many treatments, if any, you can have funded by the taxpayer. Of course, those rich enough can have any number of treatments, with an age restriction that depends on the country where you have the treatment. 60% of IVF treatment is privately funded. In the UK that age limit is currently 42. Is this fair?

4. Issues of need. Infertility isn’t an illness as the Doctor from Warrington points out above. If I spend £8,000 on an IVF treatment, this money cannot be spent screening 55 year olds for prostate cancer, which kills 11,000 men every year. How many lives could be saved if the £60m spent last year on IVF treatments was directed elsewhere?

5. Issues of wastage. We know that the money spent on IVF cycles will be wasted in 75% of cases, with the utilitarian disadvantage that any woman experiencing IVF treatment and failing to succeed is likely to suffer acute disappointment. In a perverse way, it may be that aggregate happiness might be higher if no-one had treatment at all. But there again, what of the joy of the 25% and their very wanted child? It’s always hard to balance utility and disutility on the scales of social happiness.

But there again, if we universalise infertility, it is highly likely that I would want treatment should I be unfortunate to have problems conceiving. For this reason a Kantian might well argue strongly for IVF treatment. But is the child then born a means to an end - the end being the sense of happiness and fulfilment of the parents?

Embryo wastage occurs because many eggs are fertilised and the healthiest are then implanted. Sometimes two or more are implanted, and one may then later be removed. Those who argue for the sanctity of embryonic life find this wastage of live embryos ethically unacceptable. We are back at the base point we encountered with abortion: what exactly is the moral status of an embryo or foetus, and in the end, is this a metaphysical question about beliefs rather than something resolvable by science?